Explanation of Ambiguity
Well good day Ladies and Gentleman and My
lovely Readers…came back again on Juliana’s blog. Now let me share you more and
more about “Ambiguity” but please watch this video first and enjoy with the
Explanation….
\
Kent Bach, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry
AMBIGUITY
A word, phrase, or sentence is ambiguous if
it has more than one meaning. The word 'light', for example, can mean not very
heavy or not very dark. Words like 'light', 'note', 'bear' and 'over' are lexically ambiguous.
They induce ambiguity in phrases or sentences in which they occur, such as
'light suit' and 'The duchess can't bear children'. However, phrases and
sentences can be ambiguous even if none of their constituents is. The phrase
'porcelain egg container' is structurally ambiguous, as is the
sentence 'The police shot the rioters with guns'. Ambiguity can have both a
lexical and a structural basis, as with sentences like 'I left her behind for
you' and 'He saw her duck'.
The notion of ambiguity has philosophical
applications. For example, identifying an ambiguity can aid in solving a
philosophical problem. Suppose one wonders how two people can have the same
idea, say of a unicorn. This can seem puzzling until one distinguishes 'idea'
in the sense of a particular psychological occurrence, a mental representation,
from 'idea' in the sense of an abstract, shareable concept. On the other hand,
gratuitous claims of ambiguity can make for overly simple solutions.
Accordingly, the question arises of how genuine ambiguities can be
distinguished from spurious ones. Part of the answer consists in identifying
phenomena with which ambiguity may be confused, such as vagueness, unclarity,
inexplicitness and indexicality.
1. Types of
ambiguity
2. Ambiguity
contrasted
3. Philosophical
relevance
Well Ladies and
Gentleman now the next explanation start from:
1. Types of
ambiguity
Although people are sometimes said to be
ambiguous in how they use language, ambiguity is, strictly speaking, a property
of linguistic expressions. A word, phrase, or sentence is ambiguous if it has
more than one meaning. Obviously this definition does not say what meanings are
or what it is for an expression to have one (or more than one). For a
particular language, this information is provided by a grammar, which
systematically pairs forms with meanings, ambiguous forms with more than one
meaning (see MEANING and SEMANTICS).
There are two types of ambiguity, lexical and structural.
Lexical ambiguity is by far the more common. Everyday examples include nouns
like 'chip', 'pen' and 'suit', verbs like 'call', 'draw' and 'run', and
adjectives like 'deep', 'dry' and 'hard'. There are various tests for
ambiguity. One test is having two unrelated antonyms, as with 'hard', which has
both 'soft' and 'easy' as opposites. Another is the conjunction reduction test.
Consider the sentence, 'The tailor pressed one suit in his shop and one in the
municipal court'. Evidence that the word 'suit' (not to mention 'press') is
ambiguous is provided by the anomaly of the 'crossed interpretation' of the
sentence, on which 'suit' is used to refer to an article of clothing and 'one'
to a legal action.
The above examples of ambiguity are each a
case of one word with more than one meaning. However, it is not always clear
when we have only one word. The verb 'desert' and the noun 'dessert', which
sound the same but are spelled differently, count as distinct words (they are
homonyms). So do the noun 'bear' and the verb 'bear', even though they not only
sound the same but are spelled the same. These examples may be clear cases of
homonymy, but what about the noun 'respect' and the verb 'respect' or the
preposition 'over' and the adjective 'over'? Are the members of these pairs
homonyms or different forms of the same word? There is no general consensus on
how to draw the line between cases of one ambiguous word and cases of two
homonyous words. Perhaps the difference is ultimately arbitrary.
2. Ambiguity
contrasted
It is a platitude that what your words convey
'depends on what you mean'. This suggests that one can mean different things by
what one says, but it says nothing about the variety of ways in which this is
possible. Semantic ambiguity is one such way, but there are others: homonymy
(mentioned above), vagueness, relativity, indexicality, nonliterality,
indirection and inexplicitness. All these other phenomena illustrate something
distinct from multiplicity of linguistic meaning.
An expression is vague if it admits of
borderline cases (see VAGUENESS). Terms like 'bald', 'heavy' and 'old' are
obvious examples, and their vagueness is explained by the fact that they apply
to items on fuzzy regions of a scale. Terms that express cluster concepts, like
'intelligent', 'athletic' and 'just', are vague because their instances are
determined by the application of several criteria, no one of which is decisive.
Relativity is illustrated by the words
'heavy' and 'old' (these are vague as well). Heavy people are lighter than
nonheavy elephants, and old cats can are younger than some young people. A
different sort of relativity occurs with sentences like 'Jane is finished' and
'John will be late'. Obviously one cannot be finished or late simpliciter but
only finished with something or late for something. This does not show that the
words 'finished' and 'late' are ambiguous (if they were, they would be
ambiguous in as many ways as there are things one can be finished with or
things one can be late for), but only that such a sentence is semantically
underdeterminate--it must be used to mean more than what the sentence means.
Indexical terms, like 'you', 'here' and
'tomorrow', have fixed meaning but variable reference. For example, the meaning
of the word 'tomorrow' does not change from one day to the next, though of
course its reference does (see DEMONSTRATIVES AND INDEXICALS).
Nonliterality, indirection and inexplicitness
are further ways in which what a speaker means is not uniquely determined by
what his words mean (see SPEECH ACTS). They can give rise to unclarity in
communication, as might happen with utterances of 'You're the icing on my
cake', 'I wish you could sing longer and louder', and 'Nothing is on TV
tonight'. These are not cases of linguistic ambiguity but can be confused with
it because speakers are often said to be ambiguous.
3. Philosophical
relevance
Philosophical distinctions can be obscured by
unnoticed ambiguities. So it is important to identify terms that do doubtle
duty. For example, there is a kind of ambiguity, often described as the
'act/object' or the 'process/product' ambiguity, exhibited by everyday terms
like 'building', 'shot' and 'writing'. Confusions in philosophy of language and
mind can result from overlooking this ambiguity in terms like 'inference',
'statement' and 'thought'. Another common philosophical ambiguity is the
type/token distinction. Everyday terms like 'animal', 'book' and 'car' apply
both to types and to instances (tokens) of those types. The same is true of
linguistic terms like 'sentence', 'word' and 'letter' and to philosophically
important terms like 'concept', 'event' and 'mental state' (see TYPE/TOKEN
DISTINCTION).
SOURCE:
http://online.sfsu.edu/kbach/ambguity.html
0 komentar